The Consolation of Philosophy
From Scientific American, Features | Space
An update by the author of A Universe from Nothing on his thoughts, as a theoretical physicist, about the value of the discipline of philosophy By Lawrence M. Krauss |
Recently, as a result of my most recent
book, A Universe from Nothing,
I participated in a wide-ranging and in-depth interview for The
Atlantic on
questions ranging from the nature of nothing to the best way to encourage
people to learn about the fascinating new results in cosmology. The
interview was based on the transcript of a recorded conversation and was hard
hitting (and, from my point of view, the interviewer was impressive in his
depth), but my friend Dan Dennett recently wrote to me to say that it has been
interpreted (probably because it included some verbal off-the-cuff remarks,
rather than carefully crafted written responses) by a number of his colleagues
and readers as implying a blanket condemnation of philosophy as a discipline,
something I had not intended.
Out of respect for Dan and those whom I
may have unjustly offended, and because the relationship between physics and
philosophy seems to be an area which has drawn some attention of late, I
thought I would take the opportunity to write down, as coherently as possible,
my own views on several of these issues, as a physicist and cosmologist. As
I should also make clear (and as numerous individuals have not hesitated to
comment upon already), I am not a philosopher, nor do I claim to be an expert
on philosophy. Because of a lifetime of activity in the field of
theoretical physics, ranging from particle physics to general relativity to
astrophysics, I do claim however to have some expertise in the impact of
philosophy on my own field. In any case, the level of my knowledge, and
ignorance, will undoubtedly become clearer in what follows.
As both a general reader and as someone
who is interested in ideas and culture, I have great respect for and have
learned a great deal from a number of individuals who currently classify
themselves as philosophers. Of course as a young person I read the classical
philosophers, ranging from Plato to Descartes, but as an adult I have gained
insights into the implications of brain functioning and developments in
evolutionary psychology for understanding human behavior from colleagues such
as Dan Dennett and Pat Churchland. I have been forced to re-examine my
own attitudes towards various ethical issues, from the treatment of animals to
euthanasia, by the cogent and thoughtful writing of Peter Singer. And
reading the work of my friend A.C. Grayling has immeasurably heightened my
understanding and appreciation of the human experience.
What I find common and so stimulating
about the philosophical efforts of these intellectual colleagues is the way
they thoughtfully reflect on human knowledge, amassed from empirical
explorations in areas ranging from science to history, to clarify issues that
are relevant to making decisions about how to function more effectively and
happily as an individual, and as a member of a society.
As a practicing physicist however, the
situation is somewhat different. There, I, and most of the colleagues
with whom I have discussed this matter, have found that philosophical
speculations about physics and the nature of science are not particularly
useful, and have had little or no impact upon progress in my field. Even
in several areas associated with what one can rightfully call the philosophy of
science I have found the reflections of physicists to be more useful. For
example, on the nature of science and the scientific method, I have found the
insights offered by scientists who have chosen to write concretely about their
experience and reflections, from Jacob Bronowski, to Richard Feynman, to
Francis Crick, to Werner Heisenberg, Albert Einstein, and Sir James Jeans, to
have provided me with a better practical guide than the work of even the most
significant philosophical writers of whom I am aware, such as Karl Popper and
Thomas Kuhn. I admit that this could primarily reflect of my own
philosophical limitations, but I suspect this experience is more common than
not among my scientific colleagues.
The one area of physics that has
probably sparked the most ‘philosophical’ interest in recent times is the
‘measurement’ problem in quantum mechanics. How one moves from the
remarkable and completely non-intuitive microscopic world where quantum
mechanical indeterminacy reigns supreme and particles are doing many apparently
inconsistent things at the same time, and are not localized in space or time,
to the ordered classical world of our experience where baseballs and
cannonballs have well-defined trajectories, is extremely subtle and complicated
and the issues involved have probably not been resolved to the satisfaction of
all practitioners in the field. And when one tries to apply the
rules of quantum mechanics to an entire universe, in which a separation between
observer and observed is not possible, the situation becomes even murkier.
However, even here, the most useful
progress has been made, again in my experience, by physicists. The work
of individuals such as Jim Hartle, and Murray Gell-Mann, Yakir Aharonov, Asher
Peres, John Bell and others like them, who have done careful calculations
associated with quantum measurement, has led to great progress in our
appreciation of the subtle and confusing issues of translating an underlying
quantum reality into the classical world we observe. There have
been people who one can classify as philosophers who have contributed usefully
to this discussion, such as Abner Shimony, but when they have, they have been
essentially doing physics, and have published in physics journals (Shimony’s
work as a physicist is the work I am aware of). As far as the physical
universe is concerned, mathematics and experiment, the tools of theoretical and
experimental physics appear to be the only effective ways to address questions
of principle.
Which brings me full circle to the question of nothing,
and my own comments regarding the progress of philosophy in that
regard. When it comes to the real operational issues that govern
our understanding of physical reality, ontological definitions of classical
philosophers are, in my opinion, sterile. Moreover, arguments based on
authority, be it Aristotle, or Leibniz, are irrelevant. In science, there
are no authorities, and appeal to quotes from brilliant scholars who lived
before we knew the Earth orbited the Sun, or that space can be curved, or that
dark matter or dark energy exist do not generally inform our current
understanding of nature. Empirical explorations ultimately change our
understanding of which questions are important and fruitful and which are
not.
As a scientist, the fascination normally
associated with the classically phrased question “why is there something rather
than nothing?”, is really contained in a specific operational question. That
question can be phrased as follows: How can a universe full of galaxies
and stars, and planets and people, including philosophers, arise naturally from
an initial condition in which none of these objects—no particles, no space, and
perhaps no time—may have existed? Put more succinctly perhaps: Why is
there ‘stuff’, instead of empty space? Why is there space at all?
There may be other ontological questions one can imagine but I think these are
the ‘miracles’ of creation that are so non-intuitive and remarkable, and they
are also the ‘miracles’ that physics has provided new insights about, and
spurred by amazing discoveries, has changed the playing field of our
knowledge. That we can even have plausible answers to these questions is
worth celebrating and sharing more broadly.
In this regard, there is a class of
philosophers, some theologically inspired, who object to the very fact that
scientists might presume to address any version of this fundamental ontological
issue. Recently one review of my book by such a philosopher, which I
think motivated the questions in the Atlantic interview, argued not only that
one particular version of the nothing described by modern physics was not
relevant. Even more surprisingly, this author claimed with apparent
authority (surprising because the author apparently has some background in
physics) something that is simply wrong: that the laws of physics can
never dynamically determine which particles and fields exist and whether space
itself exists, or more generally what the nature of existence might be. But
that is precisely what is possible
in the context of modern quantum field theory in curved spacetime, where a
phenomenon called ‘spontaneous symmetry breaking’ can determine dynamically
which forces manifest themselves on large scales and which particles exist as
stable states, and whether space itself can grow exponentially or not. Within
the context of quantum gravity the same is presumably true for which sorts of
universes can appear and persist. Within the context of string theory, a
similar phenomenon might ultimately determine (indeed if the theory is ever to
become predictive, it must determine) why universes might spontaneously arise
with 4 large spacetime dimensions and not 5 or 6. One cannot tell
from the review if the author actually read the book (since no mention of the
relevant cosmology is made) or simply misunderstood it.
Theologians and both Christian and
Muslim apologists have unfortunately since picked up on the ill-conceived
claims of that review to argue that physics can therefore never really address
the most profound ‘theological’ questions regarding our existence. (To
be fair, I regret sometimes lumping all philosophers in with theologians
because theology, aside from those parts that involve true historical or
linguistic scholarship, is not credible field of modern scholarship.) It
may be true that we can never fully resolved the infinite regression of ‘why
questions’ that result whenever one assumes, a priori, that our universe must have some
pre-ordained purpose. Or, to frame things in a more theological fashion:
‘Why is our Universe necessary rather than contingent?’.
One answer to this latter question can
come from physics. If all possibilities—all universes with all laws—can
arise dynamically, and if anything that is not forbidden must arise, then this
implies that both nothing and something must both exist, and we will of
necessity find ourselves amidst something. A universe like ours is, in
this context, guaranteed to arise dynamically, and we are here because we could
not ask the question if our universe weren’t here. It is in this
sense that I argued that the seemingly profound question of why there is
something rather than nothing might be actually no more profound than asking
why some flowers are red or some are blue. I was surprised
that this very claim was turned around by the reviewer as if it somehow
invalidated this possible physical resolution of the something versus nothing
conundrum.
Instead, sticking firm to the classical
ontological definition of nothing as “the absence of anything”—whatever this
means—so essential to theological, and some subset of philosophical
intransigence, strikes me as essentially sterile, backward, useless and
annoying. If “something” is a physical quantity, to be determined
by experiment, then so is ‘nothing’. It may be that even an eternal
multiverse in which all universes and laws of nature arise dynamically will
still leave open some ‘why’ questions, and therefore never fully satisfy
theologians and some philosophers. But focusing on that issue and ignoring
the remarkable progress we can make toward answering perhaps the most
miraculous aspect of the something from nothing question—understanding why
there is ‘stuff’ and not empty space, why there is space at all, and how both
stuff and space and even the forces we measure could arise from no stuff and no
space—is, in my opinion, impotent, and useless. It was in that
sense—the classical ontological claim about the nature of some abstract
nothing, compared to the physical insights about this subject that have
developed—that I made the provocative, and perhaps inappropriately broad
statement that this sort of philosophical speculation has not led to any
progress over the centuries.
What I tried to do in my writing on this
subject is carefully attempt to define precisely what scientists operationally
mean by nothing, and to differentiate between what we know, and what is merely
plausible, and what we might be able to probe in the future, and what we
cannot. The rest is, to me, just noise.
So, to those philosophers I may have
unjustly offended by seemingly blanket statements about the field, I
apologize. I value your intelligent conversation and the insights of
anyone who thinks carefully about our universe and who is willing to guide
their thinking based on the evidence of reality. To those who wish
to impose their definition of reality abstractly, independent of emerging
empirical knowledge and the changing questions that go with it, and call that
either philosophy or theology, I would say this: Please go on talking to
each other, and let the rest of us get on with the goal of learning more about
nature.
/////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////////
No hay comentarios:
Publicar un comentario